Devoir de Philosophie

Certainty

Publié le 22/02/2012

Extrait du document

'Certainty' is not a univocal term. It is predicated of people, and it is predicated of propositions. When certainty is predicated of a person, as in 'Sally is certain that she parked her car in lot 359', we are ascribing an attitude to Sally. We can say that a person, S, is psychologically certain of a proposition, p, just in case S believes p without any doubts. In general, psychological certainty has not been a topic which philosophers have found problematic. On the other hand, certainty as a property of propositions, as in 'The proposition that Sally parked her car in lot 359 is certain for Sally', has been discussed widely by philosophers. Roughly, we can say that a proposition, p, is propositionally certain for a person, S, just in case S is fully warranted in believing that p and there are no legitimate grounds whatsoever to doubt that p. The philosophical issue, of course, is whether there are any such propositions and, if so, what makes them certain.

« the 'light of nature' ).

In particular, he argued that those based upon experience (for example, 'there is a table before me' ) are never certain because there is always some legitimate basis for doubt.

Other philosophers, for example, G.E.

Moore, argued that many propositions based upon experience can be certain ( Moore, G.E.

§3 ; Commonsensism ).

The remainder of this entry discusses some of the more influential accounts of propositional certainty. A contextualist account has been developed by both Moore and Wittgenstein ( Contextualism, epistemological ). Although the specifics of the views vary, a contextualist account of propositional certainty claims, roughly, that the range of propositions that are fully warranted and beyond doubt or challenge is determined by the presuppositions of the context of discussion.

As Aristotle remarked: [Some] people demand that a reason shall be given for everything, for they seek a starting point, and they seek to get this by demonstration, while it is obvious from their actions that they have no conviction.

But their mistake is what we have stated it to be; they seek a reason for things for which no reason can be given; for the starting point of demonstration is not demonstration. (Aristotle Metaphysics : 1010a 8-14) Wittgenstein (1949-51) and Moore (1959) have argued that the proposition, 'here's one hand' , for example, is certain in most contexts.

It might not be certain if, for example, we knew that there are several fake hands resting on a table and we also know that there is a hole in the table through which people sometimes put their hands just to fool us.

But in the normal circumstances, it is certain.

(It should be noted that Wittgenstein and Moore differ about whether knowledge entails certainty.

Wittgenstein held that 'knowledge' and 'certainty' belong to different categories because knowing requires justification whereas a proposition is certain only if it does not require a justification.) Contextualism can be challenged because it blurs the distinction between psychological and propositional certainty, for the latter is characterized in a way that makes it roughly equivalent to group psychological certainty, thus eschewing the notion of epistemic warrant.

For example, in Salem, Massachusetts in the 1600s, it would have been propositionally certain (given a contextualist account) that there were witches.

But, it could be argued that although such a proposition was taken for granted, it was never fully warranted and was always subject to legitimate doubt.

More generally, it could be claimed that propositions that are certain might not be, and typically are not, equivalent to the ones that are taken for granted. A modification of the contextualist view, suggested by David Lewis (1979) , can be employed to mitigate this objection.

Let us grant the basic contextualist point that in order for genuine doubt to occur, there must be some propositions that 'stand fast' (to use Wittgenstein 's expression) which can be employed to remove or substantiate the doubt.

None the less, what stands fast at the beginning of a discussion (even if held with oneself) could become. »

↓↓↓ APERÇU DU DOCUMENT ↓↓↓